Today’s most
influential moral framework is average utilitarianism (AU for short): the idea that whatever increases the average person’s welfare is
good. It’s the default way economists use to make welfare
comparisons. It is also reflected in the use of GDP per person as a
measure of a society’s well-being.
By contrast, total
utilitarianism (TU) says that good is whatever increases the sum of
welfare. This only makes a difference when the number of people under
consideration changes. For example, 1000 people with 2 welfare units
each is better than 100 people with 3 welfare units each according to
TU, but worse according to AU. (Never mind how welfare units are
calculated or compared across people. That’s a problem for both
varieties, and for another blog post.)
John Rawls puts the
difference nicely. TU is like taking a God’s eye view of humanity
and looking at the total good in it. AU is motivated by the thought
“what if I were a randomly selected person?” So it chimes well
with contractarian, veil-of-ignorance reasoning. If you are not sure
who you will be in society, and wish to maximize your own welfare,
then maximizing average welfare could be the right thing to do.
(Rawls thought you should maximize the minimum – again, that’s
another debate.)
Another problem for TU
is that it requires a “zero point of welfare” – someone who is
just happy enough that her happiness neither adds to the total nor
subtracts from it. It’s not obvious what that zero point should be.
AU doesn’t need a zero point. You just look at whether the new
person is happier than the average.
The difference has
consequences in applied work. For example, it is often claimed that
the agricultural revolution left people worse off on average. After
agriculture, skeletons found in archaeological digs appear shorter,
and show that people were less well-nourished (this paper has some references). On the other hand,
agriculture let many more people exist on the planet. Similarly,
average incomes may have fallen in the early Industrial Revolution,
or during the British Raj in India. But at the same time, the
population increased greatly. So, did these events make the world
better or worse?
AU has a weird property
that make me suspicious of it: the evaluation in one area depends on
what happens elsewhere. Go back to the example:
State X: 100 people
with 3 utility each
State Y: 1000 people
with 2 utility each
Here, X is better than
Y. (An average of 3 beats an average of 2.) However, now add another
country where there are 100 people with 0 average utility. Now state
X has average utility of 1.5, while state Y has average utility of
about 1.8.
This is a practical
problem, because we can now only evaluate welfare at a global level.
For example a recent book claims that Soviet socialism was actually good for Soviet citizens: by reducing the birth rate,
it increased average welfare more than if the Tsars had stayed in
power. But even if the factual argument is correct, we still need to
know what was happening in the rest of the world before we can
evaluate whether socialism made the world a better place or not.
Even worse, if you are
philosophically minded: maybe the “other country” is really
another planet in a distant galaxy! Now your evaluation of even global welfare depends on some unknowable facts about the
universe. It seems more sensible to let the welfare evaluation of
states X and Y depend only on the people affected by X and Y. (TU
achieves this. To evaluate X and Y, just see which gives more total welfare to all affected people. Then by definition, that one also adds more to the total
welfare of all beings, no matter what the Martians are doing.)
Aside from measurement
trouble, it seems that as a matter of principle, evaluation of a state of affairs
should depend only on that state. Surely if X is better than Y, once
we have taken account of all the people to whom X and Y make a
difference, then it must always be so, whatever else is happening in
the world. This is a kind of “independence of irrelevant states”
principle for welfare evaluation.
I know very little about this topic. I am sure moral philosophers have
done it to death, and I would love to read a good discussion
of it.
No comments:
Post a Comment